\[
\newcommand{\C}{\mathbb{C}}
\newcommand{\haar}{\mathsf{m}}
\newcommand{\B}{\mathscr{B}}
\newcommand{\D}{\mathscr{D}}
\newcommand{\P}{\mathcal{P}}
\newcommand{\Q}{\mathbb{Q}}
\newcommand{\R}{\mathbb{R}}
\newcommand{\N}{\mathbb{N}}
\newcommand{\Z}{\mathbb{Z}}
\newcommand{\g}{>}
\newcommand{\l}{<}
\newcommand{\intd}{\,\mathsf{d}}
\newcommand{\Re}{\mathsf{Re}}
\newcommand{\area}{\mathop{\mathsf{Area}}}
\newcommand{\met}{\mathop{\mathsf{d}}}
\newcommand{\emptyset}{\varnothing}
\DeclareMathOperator{\borel}{\mathsf{Bor}}
\DeclareMathOperator{\baire}{\mathsf{Baire}}
\newcommand{\symdiff}{\mathop\triangle}
\]
Week 1 Worksheet Solutions
- Define a sequence $B_n$ in $\mathcal{P}(X)$ by $B_1 = B$ and $B_2 = A$ and $B_n = \emptyset$ for all $n \ge 3$. The sequence is pairwise disjoint and therefore
\[
\Xi(A \cup B) = \Xi \left( \, \bigcup_{n=1}^\infty B_n \right) = \sum_{n=1}^\infty \Xi(B_n) = \Xi(A) + \Xi(B)
\]
as desired.
- Let's check that $\Lambda(A-t) \ge \Lambda(A)$ for all $A \subset \R$ and all $t \in \R$. Fix $\epsilon > 0$ and let $(a_n,b_n)$ be a sequence of intervals with
\[
\Lambda(A) + \epsilon \ge \sum_{n=1}^\infty b_n - a_n
\]
and $A \subset \cup \{ (a_n,b_n) : n \in \N \}$. Certainly
\[
A-t \subset \bigcup_{n=1}^\infty (a_n-t,b_n-t)
\]
so
\[
\Lambda(A-t) \le \sum_{n=1}^\infty (b_n - t) - (a_n - t)
\]
giving $\Lambda(A-t) \le \Lambda(A) + \epsilon$.
Since $\epsilon > 0$ was arbitrary we get $\Lambda(A-t) \le \Lambda(A)$. Replacing $A$ with $A-t$ and $t$ with $-t$ gives the converse inequality, establishing the desired equality.
- We need the following fact, which can be proved by induction: if
\[
[r,s] \subset (a_1,b_1) \cup \cdots \cup (a_n,b_n)
\]
then
\[
s-r \le \sum_{k=1}^n b_k - a_k
\]
holds.
Now fix a sequence $n \mapsto (a_n,b_n)$ of intervals that satisfies
\[
\Lambda([0,1]) + \epsilon \ge \sum_{n=1}^\infty b_n - a_n
\]
and covers $[0,1]$.
By compactness we can find numbers $r(1) \l \cdots \l r(k)$ with
\[
[0,1] \subset \bigcup_{i=1}^k (a_{r(i)}, b_{r(i)})
\]
so we can say that
\[
\Lambda([0,1]) + \epsilon \ge \sum_{i=1}^k b_{r(i)} - a_{r(i)} \ge 1
\]
using the fact above. As $\epsilon > 0$ was arbitrary we are done.
- We verify directly the three defining properties. The first is that $X$ belongs to the collection, which is explicitly the case. The second is that complements of sets in $\{\emptyset, X\}$ also belong to $\{\emptyset, X\}$: we can check this directly for each set in the collection, because $X \setminus \emptyset = X$ and $X \setminus X = \emptyset$. Lastly, let $n \mapsto B_n$ be a sequence in $\{\emptyset, X\}$. Each $B_n$ is therefore either $\emptyset$ of $X$. If all are the empty set then their union is also empty and belongs to $\{\emptyset, X\}$. If any one of them is $X$ then their union is also $X$ and again the union belongs to $\{\emptyset, X \}$.
- Fix a measurable space $(X,\B)$. Given a sequence $B_1,B_2,B_3,\dots$ in $\B$ define
\[
\begin{aligned}
\limsup_n B_n &= \bigcap_{N \in \N} \bigcup_{j \ge N} B_j \\
\liminf_n B_n &= \bigcup_{N \in \N} \bigcap_{j \ge N} B_j
\end{aligned}
\]
- A point belongs to the limit supremum if there are infinitely many $n \in \N$ such that $x \in B_n$. A points belongs to the limit inferior if there are only finitely many $n \in \N$ for which $B_n$ does not contain $x$.
- If $x$ belongs to the limit inferior then are certainly infinitely many $n$ for which $x$ belongs to $B_n$.
- They both belong to $\B$ because we cannot leave $\B$ by taking countable unions and countable intersections.
-
- $[0,1] = \R \setminus (-\infty,0) \cap \R \setminus (1,\infty)$ is Borel.
- $[0,1] \cup (3,5)$ is neither open nor closed.
- The set $\R \setminus \Q$ of irrational numbers is not open and therefore not a countable union of open sets. It is also not the countable union of closed sets $F_1,F_2,\dots$ because if it were then
\[
\R = \bigcup_{n \in \N} F_n \cup \bigcup_{q \in \Q} \{q\}
\]
would be a countable union of closed sets each having empty interior, which is impossible. (See next question!)
-
- Since every singleton set $\{b\}$ is nowhere dense, every countable set is a countable union of nowhere dense sets and therefore meagre.
- Since $\R$ is a complete metric space, it is impossible by the Baire category theorem to write $\R$ as a countable union of nowhere dense sets.
- The whole set $\R$ is open, so it belongs to the Baire σ-algebra. Since
\[
\left( \, \bigcup_{n=1}^\infty B_n \right) \triangle \left( \, \bigcup_{n=1}^\infty U_n \right) \subset \bigcup_{n=1}^\infty B_n \triangle U_n
\]
and a countable union of meagre sets is meagre, it is true that a countable union of Baire sets is a Baire set.
It remains to show that the complement of a Baire set is also a Baire set. Suppose that $B$ is a Baire set. There is an open set $U$ such that $B \triangle U$ is meagre. Let $V$ be the complement of the closure of $U$. Then $V$ is open and
\[
(\R \setminus B) \triangle (\R \setminus V) = B \triangle V \subset (B \triangle U) \cup \partial U
\]
so it suffices to prove that the frontier $\partial U$ of an open set is nowhere dense. As $\partial U$ is closed, so we just need to prove that $\partial U$ has empty interior. Suppose, to reach a contradiction, that $B(x,r)$ is contained in $\partial U$. By definition of $\partial U$ the ball $B(x,r)$ intersects $U$. But then the open intersection $U \cap B(x,r)$ must contain some $B(y,s)$ which is contradicts the definition of $\partial U$.
- Every open set is a Baire set. Since $\baire(\R)$ is a σ-algebra, it must therefore contain the smallest σ-algebra that contains the open sets i.e. the Borel σ-algebra.
-
- The cardinality of $\borel(\R)$ is the same as the cardinality of $\R$.
- The cardinality of the power set $\P(\mathcal{C})$ of the middle-thirds Cantor set $\mathcal{C}$ is strictly greater than the cardinality of $\R$ because $\mathcal{C}$ is uncountable. As the cardinality of $\mathcal{P}(\mathcal{C})$ is strictly greater than the cardinality of $\borel(\R)$ it is false that every subset of $\mathcal{C}$ is a Borel set.